Using Political Ideas -  Barbara Goodwin

Using Political Ideas (eBook)

eBook Download: EPUB
2012 | 5. Auflage
460 Seiten
Wiley (Verlag)
978-1-118-52946-1 (ISBN)
Systemvoraussetzungen
31,20 inkl. MwSt
  • Download sofort lieferbar
  • Zahlungsarten anzeigen
'Comprehensive, and covers the main ideologies in an interesting way . . . takes a critical and engaging perspective . . . framed in the context of debates around the meaning and purpose of theoretical enquiry . . . a more rewarding read than its competitors.'
--Madeleine Davis, Department of Politics, Queen Mary, University of London.
'This book is pitched at a good level for bright and interested undergraduates . . . the combination of ideologies and concepts in one book is a major selling point.'
--Professor Paul Taggart, Professor of Politics, University of Sussex
'Pulls off the enviable coup of being scholarly and yet not scary as well as providing genuinely fresh insights for the more familiar reader.'
--Dr Peter Handley, School of Political, Social, and International Studies, University of East Anglia
'An outstandingly useful text . . . I look forward to a fifth edition being made available'
--Mark Donovan, Senior Lecturer in Politics, University of Cardiff
Using Political Ideas is a unique blend of political philosophy, political theory and history of political thought. It combines a critique of the major ideologies of recent and contemporary society with an analysis of the ideas that form the very stuff of political debate. By exposing the interplay between ideas and ideologies, it shows why political opponents often speak at cross-purposes and why rational agreement is so hard to achieve in politics.
The fifth edition of this well respected and widely known text will be welcomed by all those interested in questions such as:
* Is equality more important than personal freedom?
* Does the majority have the right to dictate to the minority in multicultural society?
* Is nationalism a progressive force in the world?
With a new chapter on the political ideologies of the twenty-first century, and greater emphasis on contemporary issues such as multiculturalism, citizenship and identity throughout the book, this new edition is the ideal starting point for students and anyone else who needs an introduction to political thought.

Barbara Goodwin is Professor of Politics at the University of East Anglia, Norwich. Her books include Justice by Lottery (2nd edn. 2005) and Ethics at Work (2000) and several books on the political importance of utopian ideas. She has broadcast two series of programmes about democracy on the BBC World Service. Her interests range widely in politics, philosophy and social science.

Cover 1
Half Title page 2
Title page 3
Copyright page 4
Preface to the Fifth Edition 6
Part I: Introduction 7
Chapter 1: What is Political Theory? 8
Notes 8
Further Reading 8
Chapter 2: Ideology 19
Marx on Ideology 19
‘Ideology’ Since Marx 19
Conceptual Problems 19
Notes 19
Further Reading 19
Part II: Ideologies 31
Chapter 3: Liberalism 32
The Ingredients of Liberalism 32
The Liberal Model: Perpetual Motion? 32
Why Does the Liberal Value the Individual so Highly? 32
Do I Know My Own Interests? 32
Liberals and Welfare States 32
Liberalism Today 32
Notes 32
Further Reading 32
Chapter 4: Marxism 54
Problems in Reading Marx 54
The Vocabulary of the Dialectic 54
Marx’s Economics 54
The Social Consequences 54
History and Revolution 54
Communist Society 54
Criticizing Marx 54
The Evolution of Marxism 54
Revisionism and Recantation 54
Notes 54
Further Reading 54
Chapter 5: Socialism 78
The Nucleus of Socialism 78
The Changing Face of Socialism 78
Objections to Socialism 78
The Contradictions of Social Democracy 78
Notes 78
Further Reading 78
Chapter 6: Anarchism 96
The Critique of Authority 96
The Anarchist Order 96
The Moral Basis of Anarchist Society 96
Freedom Within Society 96
Order Without Dependence 96
Anarchist Individualism 96
Anarchist Values 96
Contemporary Anarchism 96
Objections to Anarchist Theory 96
The Ethics of Violence 96
Notes 96
Further Reading 96
Chapter 7: Conservatism 115
Against Change 115
The Virtues of Tradition 115
Human Imperfection and Inequality 115
Conservative Politics 115
The Conservative Mentality 115
Conservatism Today 115
Ideology or Intuition? 115
Notes 115
Further Reading 115
Chapter 8: Totalitarianism 131
The Phenomenological Approach 131
The Socio-Historical Approach 131
The Essentialist Analysis 131
The Fascist Example 131
The Psychological Roots of Totalitarianism 131
Totalitarianism Dissolved 131
Notes 131
Further Reading 131
Chapter 9: Feminism 146
The Demonization of Women, and of Feminism 146
Feminists and Human Nature 146
Gendered Society 146
Patriarchal Society 146
Women and Capitalism 146
Oppression 146
Feminist Strategies 146
Feminism as Ideology 146
Notes 146
Further Reading 146
Chapter 10: Green Ideologies 172
Shades of Green 172
Economic Arguments 172
Anti-Pollution Arguments 172
Moral Arguments 172
Green Utopias 172
Problematic Questions 172
Green Successes 172
Notes 172
Further Reading 172
Chapter 11: Beyond Ideology: Nationalism 192
What is a Nation? 192
The Incoherence of Nationalism 192
The Origins of Nationalism 192
Is Nationalism an Ideology? 192
Nationalism, Liberalism and Democracy 192
Rights of Secession 192
Objections to Nationalism 192
Notes 192
Further Reading 192
Part III: Ideas 207
Chapter 12: Democracy 208
The Classical Ideal 208
Elitists and Pluralists 208
‘Radical’ Democracy 208
Democracy’s Paradox 208
The Problem of Minorities 208
Democracy and Liberalism 208
Democracy and Truth 208
The Will of the People 208
New Forms of Democracy 208
Notes 208
Further Reading 208
Chapter 13: Power, Authority and the State 233
What is Power? 233
What Creates Authority? 233
Power and Authority 233
The State Leviathan 233
Notes 233
Further Reading 233
Chapter 14: Freedom and Rights 247
The Meaning of Freedom 247
Varieties of Freedom 247
Freedom and Illusion 247
The ‘Rights of Man’ 247
Human Rights 247
Special Rights for Women? 247
Rights and Liberty 247
The Climate of Tolerance 247
Notes 247
Further Reading 247
Chapter 15: Citizenship, Obligation and Protest 266
Contractual Obligation 266
The Just Government 266
Self-Interest and Gratitude 266
Why Do I Obey the Law? 266
The Right to Protest 266
The Scope of Protest 266
The Right of Revolution 266
Notes 266
Further Reading 266
Chapter 16: Social Justice and Equality 285
The Criteria for Justice 285
Liberal, Socialist and ‘Natural’ Justice 285
Retributive Justice 285
What is Justice? 285
Nations and Generations 285
Justice and Equality 285
Notes 285
Further Reading 285
Chapter 17: New Political Dimensions 304
Religion and Politics 304
Multiculturalism, Diversity and Identity Politics 304
Globalization and Global Terrorism 304
Notes 304
Further Reading 304
About the Author 311
Index of Concepts and Proper Names 312

CHAPTER 2


IDEOLOGY


‘Ideology’ must be the most overworked word in political debate. The word has been drained of most of its analytic content and has become a mere label to be tied on doctrines which we dislike. ‘Ideological’ is rarely used except pejoratively, as a synonym for ‘doctrinaire’ and ‘dogmatic’. But the contention of this book is that all coherent political doctrines are ideological, as is our use of political ideas themselves: if this is accepted, the pejorative connotations of the term must be laid aside. This chapter examines the various concepts of ideology which have developed, and their significance for political theory.

The debate about what ideology actually is is traced historically in this chapter, as it is in some ways a debate primarily located in the past two centuries. Today, many thinkers would contend that we are in a ‘post-ideological’ era, and would agree with Fukuyama that liberalism has won the struggle between ideologies and is the only game in town.1 That claim must be contested, since emerging ideologies such as religio-political doctrines, which could be considered ideological, Green ideologies and the anti-globalization movement pose major challenges to the supposed liberal-democratic hegemony.

MARX ON IDEOLOGY


The term ‘ideology’ literally means ‘the science of ideas’ but in the early nineteenth century a more critical usage was established: it came to mean an abstract, visionary or speculative way of thinking. While it was Marx who offered the first major analysis of ideology as such, the philosophical problem which gave rise to the notion had been widely debated during the Enlightenment. The problem is that of the status of knowledge. Many previous cultures had believed knowledge to be certain, absolute and objective: Plato thought that there existed in some metaphysical dimension Ideas or Forms, absolute truths which served as models which men should strive to realize in society. The knowledge of these Ideas (such as Justice and the Good) was absolute knowledge, attainable through philosophical contemplation. Despite its pre-Christian origins, Platonism later influenced the Christian view of knowledge and truth. Mediaeval Christian theology held that truth was God-given and absolute, reflecting the divinely ordained and fixed order of the world. The chief source of such knowledge was the scriptures, although during the Renaissance the experimental, scientific method of gaining knowledge was reconciled with Christian precepts. According to both Platonic and Christian views, knowledge ‘exists’ independently or emanates from a non-human source, and so is objectively established. Knowledge is to be discovered, not created, by human beings.

Enlightenment philosophers, many of whom were atheists, used reason as an implement for destroying the prejudices and mysteries of Christianity, arguing that the world was in principle explicable scientifically. A new conception of knowledge resulted: the thinking being was seen as the creator of knowledge. Kant and Hegel developed theories of knowledge, epistemologies, on the basis of this insight, which abolished the polarity between the individual as a thinking subject, passively absorbing objective knowledge, and the external world, the source and object of knowledge. The new theories emphasized the subjective aspect of knowledge: the thinker inevitably intrudes herself into her perception of the object which she is trying to know. This had been implicit in Locke’s argument, a century before, that knowledge of the external world is gained through our senses and so is sense-dependent, and therefore subject-dependent: for example, given a different eye structure, the world would appear to us as black and white. Kant emphasized that knowledge results from an active process, not mere passive absorption of data, while Hegel’s dialectical account of knowledge described the constant dialogue between the conscious subject and the object, each stage raising the subject to a higher form of knowledge.

Marx’s achievement was to codify the ways in which the social identity of the ‘knowing subject’ altered her knowledge, and to describe the process of knowing in concrete terms. As a materialist, he believed that material causes could be found for all events and phenomena in the world: there were no mysterious or metaphysical events and everything was scientifically explicable, including humankind. All human thought, ideas and theories (in general, ‘consciousness’) were determined by material factors and, more precisely, by social circumstances.

Consciousness is, therefore, from the very beginning, a social product, and remains so as long as men exist at all.2

Marx considered that the economic structure of society determined all its other aspects, from social relations and political institutions to law, morality and knowledge itself. Each economic system gave rise to the existence of classes in society, and people’s knowledge and beliefs were determined not only by the general social context but by their particular class position in society. In propounding this materialist theory of consciousness, Marx challenged the ‘Young Hegelians’ and, indirectly, Hegel himself, who were, by contrast, idealists. They believed that ideas had an autonomous existence and could act as independent causes of events in the material world: the intellect had priority over mere physical existence. Revolutions, even, were made by ideas. Hegel had seen history as the movement of ‘Spirit’ through the world, realizing itself in different social forms. Marx thought such idealism (not to be confused with ‘idealism’ in the sense of ‘the pursuit of ideals’, although the two meanings are related) illusory and philosophically false.

Marx never set out his theory of ideology systematically in one text, but a coherent doctrine can be extrapolated from his works. Social reality itself is contradictory, Marx held: capitalism fosters two antagonistic classes, the bourgeoisie and the proletariat, whose interests are diametrically opposed, and which will finally come into direct conflict. Ideology is a resolution of these contradictions in the mind: thus, capitalist ideology may ‘resolve’ class conflict by emphasizing the common interests and harmony between the classes, or the ‘organic’ nature of society, but this cannot alter the real antagonism between the interests of those classes. Because ideology tries to resolve the irresoluble, it gives an inaccurate and distorted representation of material reality.

The elaboration of this general conception of ideology shows what Marx thought its social functions to be. An individual’s consciousness is determined by his class position, his ownership or non-ownership of the means of production, and the social relationships into which he enters as a member of a certain class. Marx gave an account of the genesis of different class viewpoints in economic circumstances, showing how each point of view distorts reality according to its own interests. His dialectical view of social processes (discussed in Chapter 4) entailed that in every conflict the opposing classes or groups had their own partial understanding of the process: he described the production process from the viewpoint of the capitalist and from that of the labourer, showing the differences between these subjective, one-sided accounts of the same phenomenon.3 Because such knowledge was bound up with the knower’s class position, it was necessarily a partial and inaccurate representation of the world: hence, it was ideological. For Marx, the only escape route from ideology to accurate knowledge was via a synthetic account which comprehended both sides of the process, as did his own theory, which he designated ‘scientific’, in contradistinction to ‘ideological’ social theory.

Under capitalism, the bourgeoisie reinforces its dominant position in the economy by all possible social and political means, including the creation of the state. Ideology is viewed by Marx as a major instrument of repression in the hands of the ruling class, used to deceive subordinate classes about the true nature of capitalism and to perpetuate its own domination. The law, religion, morality, social theory and philosophy all evolve or are refashioned so as to reflect the bourgeois standpoint, and they become part of the wider ideology, functioning to disguise the contradictions in society and the grievances and discontent of the proletariat. Although the worker’s class position should give him a set of ideas which reflect his own reality, he may instead absorb the all-pervasive bourgeois ideology which misleads him as to his own (exploited) situation: then, he is said to be the victim of false consciousness, which makes him unlikely to rebel against his oppressed condition. The idea of ‘inverted’ or false consciousness attributed to Marx did not mean anything so simple as the direct deliberate deception of gullible proletarians by a malevolent bourgeoisie. Bourgeois ideology invades the consciousness of workers through the propagation of commonsensical, seemingly non-dogmatic ideas, such as ‘Everyone should pay their way’, which establish the work ethic, the consumption ethic and the ideal of the ‘self-made man’, all of which are vital to capitalism. A doctrine of individualism likewise develops which teaches that we establish our personal...

Erscheint lt. Verlag 21.12.2012
Sprache englisch
Themenwelt Sozialwissenschaften Politik / Verwaltung
ISBN-10 1-118-52946-4 / 1118529464
ISBN-13 978-1-118-52946-1 / 9781118529461
Haben Sie eine Frage zum Produkt?
EPUBEPUB (Adobe DRM)
Größe: 879 KB

Kopierschutz: Adobe-DRM
Adobe-DRM ist ein Kopierschutz, der das eBook vor Mißbrauch schützen soll. Dabei wird das eBook bereits beim Download auf Ihre persönliche Adobe-ID autorisiert. Lesen können Sie das eBook dann nur auf den Geräten, welche ebenfalls auf Ihre Adobe-ID registriert sind.
Details zum Adobe-DRM

Dateiformat: EPUB (Electronic Publication)
EPUB ist ein offener Standard für eBooks und eignet sich besonders zur Darstellung von Belle­tristik und Sach­büchern. Der Fließ­text wird dynamisch an die Display- und Schrift­größe ange­passt. Auch für mobile Lese­geräte ist EPUB daher gut geeignet.

Systemvoraussetzungen:
PC/Mac: Mit einem PC oder Mac können Sie dieses eBook lesen. Sie benötigen eine Adobe-ID und die Software Adobe Digital Editions (kostenlos). Von der Benutzung der OverDrive Media Console raten wir Ihnen ab. Erfahrungsgemäß treten hier gehäuft Probleme mit dem Adobe DRM auf.
eReader: Dieses eBook kann mit (fast) allen eBook-Readern gelesen werden. Mit dem amazon-Kindle ist es aber nicht kompatibel.
Smartphone/Tablet: Egal ob Apple oder Android, dieses eBook können Sie lesen. Sie benötigen eine Adobe-ID sowie eine kostenlose App.
Geräteliste und zusätzliche Hinweise

Zusätzliches Feature: Online Lesen
Dieses eBook können Sie zusätzlich zum Download auch online im Webbrowser lesen.

Buying eBooks from abroad
For tax law reasons we can sell eBooks just within Germany and Switzerland. Regrettably we cannot fulfill eBook-orders from other countries.

Mehr entdecken
aus dem Bereich
Mein Leben in der Politik

von Wolfgang Schäuble

eBook Download (2024)
Klett-Cotta (Verlag)
29,99